ART

In mathematics, logic, and computer science, a type system is a formal system in which every term has a "type" which defines its meaning and the operations that may be performed on it. Type theory is the academic study of type systems.

Some type theories can serve as alternatives to set theory as a foundation of mathematics. Two well-known such theories are Alonzo Church's typed λ-calculus and Per Martin-Löf's intuitionistic type theory.

Type theory was created to avoid paradoxes in previous foundations such as naive set theory, formal logics and rewrite systems.

Type theory is closely related to, and in some cases overlaps with, computational type systems, which are a programming language feature used to reduce bugs.

History
Main article: History of type theory

Between 1902 and 1908 Bertrand Russell proposed various "theories of type" in response to his discovery that Gottlob Frege's version of naive set theory was afflicted with Russell's paradox. By 1908 Russell arrived at a "ramified" theory of types together with an "axiom of reducibility" both of which featured prominently in Whitehead and Russell's Principia Mathematica published between 1910 and 1913. They attempted to resolve Russell's paradox by first creating a hierarchy of types, then assigning each concrete mathematical (and possibly other) entity to a type. Entities of a given type are built exclusively from entities of those types that are lower in their hierarchy, thus preventing an entity from being assigned to itself.

In the 1920s, Leon Chwistek and Frank P. Ramsey proposed an unramified type theory, now known as the "theory of simple types" or simple type theory, which collapsed the hierarchy of the types in the earlier ramified theory and as such did not require the axiom of reducibility.

The common usage of "type theory" is when those types are used with a term rewrite system. The most famous early example is Alonzo Church's simply typed lambda calculus. Church's theory of types[1] helped the formal system avoid the Kleene–Rosser paradox that afflicted the original untyped lambda calculus. Church demonstrated that it could serve as a foundation of mathematics and it was referred to as a higher-order logic.

Some other type theories include Per Martin-Löf's intuitionistic type theory, which has been the foundation used in some areas of constructive mathematics. Thierry Coquand's calculus of constructions and its derivatives are the foundation used by Coq, Lean, and others. The field is an area of active research, as demonstrated by homotopy type theory.

Basic concepts
Main article: Lambda cube

The contemporary presentation of type systems in the context of type theory has been made systematic by a conceptual framework introduced by Henk Barendregt[2].
Type, term, value

In a system of type theory, a term is opposed to a type. For example, 4, 2+2, and \( {\displaystyle 2\cdot 2} \) are all separate terms with the type \( \mathrm {nat} \) for natural numbers. Traditionally, the term is followed by a colon and its type, such as \( 2:\mathrm {nat} \)- this means that the number 2 is of type\( \mathrm {nat} \) . Beyond this opposition and syntax, little can be said about types in this generality, but often, they are interpreted as some kind of collection (not necessarily sets) of the values that the term might evaluate to. It is usual to denote terms by e and types by \( \tau \) . How terms and types are shaped depends on the particular type system and is made precise by some syntax and additional restrictions of well-formedness.

Typing environment, type assignment, type judgement
Main article: Typing environment

Typing usually takes place in some context or environment denoted by the symbol \( \Gamma \). Often, an environment is a list of pairs \( {\displaystyle e:\tau } \). This pair is sometimes called an assignment. The context completes the above opposition. Together they form a judgement denoted \( {\displaystyle \Gamma \vdash e:\tau } \).

Rewriting rules, conversion, reduction

Type theories have explicit computation and it is encoded in rules for rewriting terms. These are called conversion rules or, if the rule only works in one direction, a reduction rule. For example, 2+2 and 4 are syntactically different terms, but the former reduces to the latter. This reduction is written \( {\displaystyle 2+2\twoheadrightarrow 4} \). These rules also establishes corresponding equivalences between the term, written \( {\displaystyle 2+2\equiv 4}. \)

The term 2+1 reduces to 3. Since 3 cannot be reduced further, it is called a normal form. Various systems of typed lambda calculus including the simply typed lambda calculus, Jean-Yves Girard's System F, and Thierry Coquand's calculus of constructions are strongly normalizing. In such systems, a successful type check implies a termination proof of the term.

Type rules
Main article: Type rule

Based on the judgements and equivalences type inference rules can be used to describe how a type system assigns a type to a syntactic constructions (terms), much like in natural deduction. To be meaningful, conversion and type rules are usually closely related as in e.g. by a subject reduction property, which might establish a part of the soundness of a type system.
Decision problems

A type system is naturally associated with the decision problems of type checking, typability, and type inhabitation.[3]

Type checking
Main article: Type checking

The decision problem of type checking (abbreviated by \( {\displaystyle \Gamma \vdash e:\tau ?}) \) is:

Given a type environment \( \Gamma \) , a term e, and a type \( \tau \) , decide whether the term can be assigned the type \( \tau \) in the type environment \( \Gamma \).

Decidability of type checking means that type safety of any given program text (source code) can be verified.

Typability
Main article: Typability

The decision problem of typability (abbreviated by \( {\displaystyle \exists \Gamma ,\tau .\Gamma \vdash e:\tau ?}) \) is:

Given a term e, decide whether there exists a type environment \( \Gamma \) and a type \( \tau \) such that the term e can be assigned the type \( \tau \) in the type environment \( \Gamma \).

A variant of typability is typability wrt. a type environment (abbreviated by \( {\displaystyle \exists \tau .\Gamma \vdash e:\tau ?} \) ) , for which a type environment is part of the input. If the given term does not contain external references (such as free term variables), then typability coincides with typability wrt. the empty type environment.

Typability is closely related to type inference. Whereas typability (as a decision problem) addresses the existence of a type for a given term, type inference (as a computation problem) requires an actual type to be computed.
Type inhabitation
Main article: Type inhabitation

The decision problem of type inhabitation (abbreviated by \( {\displaystyle \exists e.\Gamma \vdash e:\tau ?}) \) is:

Given a type environment \( \Gamma \) and a type \( \tau \) , decide whether there exists a term e that can be assigned the type \( \tau \) in the type environment\( \Gamma \).

Girard's paradox shows, that type inhabitation is strongly related to the consistency of a type system with Curry–Howard correspondence. To be sound, such a system must have uninhabited types.

The opposition of terms and types can also be views as one of implementation and specification. By program synthesis (the computational counterpart of) type inhabitation (see below) can be used to construct (all or parts of) programs from specification given in form of type information.[4]
Interpretations of type theory

Type theory is closely linked to many fields of active research. Most particular, the Curry–Howard correspondence provides a deep isomorphism between intuitionistic logic, typed lambda calculus and cartesian closed categories.
Intuitionistic logic
Main article: Curry–Howard correspondence

Beside the view of types as collection of values of a term, type theory offers a second interpretation of the opposition of term and types. Types can be seen as propositions and terms as proofs. In this way of reading a typing, a function type \( \alpha \rightarrow \beta \) is viewed as an implication, i.e. as the proposition, that \( \beta \) follows from \( \alpha \)
.
Category theory
Main article: Cartesian closed category

The internal language of the cartesian closed category is the simply typed lambda calculus. This view can be extend to other typed lambda calculi. Certain Cartesian closed categories, the topoi, have been proposed as a general setting for mathematics, instead of traditional set theory.
Difference from set theory

There are many different set theories and many different systems of type theory, so what follows are generalizations.

Set theory is built on top of logic. It requires a separate system like predicate logic underneath it. In type theory, concepts like "and" and "or" can be encoded as types in the type theory itself.
In set theory, an element is not restricted to one set. In type theory, terms (generally) belong to only one type. (Where a subset would be used, type theory tends to use a predicate function that returns true if the term is in the subset and returns false if the value is not. The union of two types can be defined as a new type called a sum type, which contains new terms.)
Set theory usually encodes numbers as sets. (0 is the empty set, 1 is a set containing the empty set, etc. See Set-theoretic definition of natural numbers.) Type theory can encode numbers as functions using Church encoding or more naturally as inductive types. Inductive types create new constants for the successor function and zero, closely resembling Peano's axioms.
Type theory has a simple connection to constructive mathematics through the BHK interpretation. It can be connected to logic by the Curry–Howard isomorphism. And some type theories are closely connected to Category theory.

Optional features
Dependent types
Main article: Dependent types

A dependent type is a type that depends on a term or another type. Thus, the type returned by a function may depend on the argument to the function.

For example, a list of\( \mathrm {nat} \) s of length 4 may be a different type than a list of\( \mathrm {nat} \) s of length 5. In a type theory with dependent types, it is possible to define a function that takes a parameter "n" and returns a list containing "n" zeros. Calling the function with 4 would produce a term with a different type than if the function was called with 5.

Dependent types play a central role in intuitionistic type theory and in the design of functional programming languages like Idris, ATS, Agda and Epigram.

Equality types

Many systems of type theory have a type that represents equality of types and of terms. This type is different from convertibility, and is often denoted propositional equality.

In intuitionistic type theory, the equality type (also called the identity type) is known as I for identity. There is a type \( I\ A\ a\ b \) when A is a type and a and b are both terms of type A. A term of type \( I\ A\ a\ b \) is interpreted as meaning that a is equal to b.

In practice, it is possible to build a type \( I\ \mathrm {nat} \ 3\ 4 \)but there will not exist a term of that type. In intuitionistic type theory, new terms of equality start with reflexivity. If 3 {\displaystyle 3} 3 is a term of type\( \mathrm {nat} \) , then there exists a term of type \( I\ \mathrm {nat} \ 3\ 3. \) More complicated equalities can be created by creating a reflexive term and then doing a reduction on one side. So if 2 2+1 is a term of type\( \mathrm {nat} \) , then there is a term of type \( I\ \mathrm {nat} \ (2+1)\ (2+1) \) and, by reduction, generate a term of type \( I\ \mathrm {nat} \ (2+1)\ 3 \). Thus, in this system, the equality type denotes that two values of the same type are convertible by reductions.

Having a type for equality is important because it can be manipulated inside the system. There is usually no judgement to say two terms are not equal; instead, as in the Brouwer–Heyting–Kolmogorov interpretation, we map \( \neg (a=b) \) to\( (a=b)\to \bot \) , where \( \bot \) is the bottom type having no values. There exists a term with typ\( (I\ \mathrm {nat} \ 3\ 4)\to \bot \), but not one of type \( (I\ \mathrm {nat} \ 3\ 3)\to \bot \).

Homotopy type theory differs from intuitionistic type theory mostly by its handling of the equality type.
Inductive types
Main article: Inductive type

A system of type theory requires some basic terms and types to operate on. Some systems build them out of functions using Church encoding. Other systems have inductive types: a set of base types and a set of type constructors that generate types with well-behaved properties. For example, certain recursive functions called on inductive types are guaranteed to terminate.

Coinductive types are infinite data types created by giving a function that generates the next element(s). See Coinduction and Corecursion.

Induction-induction is a feature for declaring an inductive type and a family of types which depends on the inductive type.

Induction recursion allows a wider range of well-behaved types, allowing the type and recursive functions operating on it to be defined at the same time.
Universe types

Types were created to prevent paradoxes, such as Russell's paradox. However, the motives that lead to those paradoxes—being able to say things about all types—still exist. So, many type theories have a "universe type", which contains all other types (and not itself).

In systems where you might want to say something about universe types, there is a hierarchy of universe types, each containing the one below it in the hierarchy. The hierarchy is defined as being infinite, but statements must only refer to a finite number of universe levels.

Type universes are particularly tricky in type theory. The initial proposal of intuitionistic type theory suffered from Girard's paradox.
Computational component

Many systems of type theory, such as the simply-typed lambda calculus, intuitionistic type theory, and the calculus of constructions, are also programming languages. That is, they are said to have a "computational component". The computation is the reduction of terms of the language using rewriting rules.

A system of type theory that has a well-behaved computational component also has a simple connection to constructive mathematics through the BHK interpretation.

Non-constructive mathematics in these systems is possible by adding operators on continuations such as call with current continuation. However, these operators tend to break desirable properties such as canonicity and parametricity.
Type theories
Major

Simply typed lambda calculus which is a higher-order logic;
intuitionistic type theory;
system F;
LF is often used to define other type theories;
calculus of constructions and its derivatives.

Minor

Automath;
ST type theory;
UTT (Lao's Unified Theory of dependent Types)
some forms of combinatory logic;
others defined in the lambda cube;
others under the name typed lambda calculus;
others under the name pure type system.

Active

Homotopy type theory is being researched.

Practical impact
Programming languages
Main article: Type system

There is extensive overlap and interaction between the fields of type theory and type systems. Type systems are a programming language feature designed to identify bugs. Any static program analysis, such as the type checking algorithms in the semantic analysis phase of compiler, has a connection to type theory.

A prime example is Agda, a programming language which uses UTT (Luo's Unified Theory of dependent Types) for its type system. The programming language ML was developed for manipulating type theories (see LCF) and its own type system was heavily influenced by them.
Mathematical foundations

The first computer proof assistant, called Automath, used type theory to encode mathematics on a computer. Martin-Löf specifically developed intuitionistic type theory to encode all mathematics to serve as a new foundation for mathematics. There is ongoing research into mathematical foundations using homotopy type theory.

Mathematicians working in category theory already had difficulty working with the widely accepted foundation of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. This led to proposals such as Lawvere's Elementary Theory of the Category of Sets (ETCS).[5] Homotopy type theory continues in this line using type theory. Researchers are exploring connections between dependent types (especially the identity type) and algebraic topology (specifically homotopy).

Proof assistants
Main article: Proof assistant

Much of the current research into type theory is driven by proof checkers, interactive proof assistants, and automated theorem provers. Most of these systems use a type theory as the mathematical foundation for encoding proofs, which is not surprising, given the close connection between type theory and programming languages:

LF is used by Twelf, often to define other type theories;
many type theories which fall under higher-order logic are used by the HOL family of provers and PVS;
computational type theory is used by NuPRL;
calculus of constructions and its derivatives are used by Coq, Matita, and Lean;
UTT (Luo's Unified Theory of dependent Types) is used by Agda which is both a programming language and proof assistant

Many type theories are supported by LEGO and Isabelle. Isabelle also supports foundations besides type theories, such as ZFC. Mizar is an example of a proof system that only supports set theory.
Linguistics

Type theory is also widely used in formal theories of semantics of natural languages, especially Montague grammar and its descendants. In particular, categorial grammars and pregroup grammars extensively use type constructors to define the types (noun, verb, etc.) of words.

The most common construction takes the basic types e and t for individuals and truth-values, respectively, and defines the set of types recursively as follows:

if a and b are types, then so is \( \langle a,b\rangle \) ;
nothing except the basic types, and what can be constructed from them by means of the previous clause are types.

A complex type \( \langle a,b\rangle \) is the type of functions from entities of type a to entities of type b. Thus one has types like \( \langle e,t\rangle \) which are interpreted as elements of the set of functions from entities to truth-values, i.e. indicator functions of sets of entities. An expression of type \( \langle \langle e,t\rangle ,t\rangle \)is a function from sets of entities to truth-values, i.e. a (indicator function of a) set of sets. This latter type is standardly taken to be the type of natural language quantifiers, like everybody or nobody (Montague 1973, Barwise and Cooper 1981).
Social sciences

Gregory Bateson introduced a theory of logical types into the social sciences; his notions of double bind and logical levels are based on Russell's theory of types.
Relation to category theory

Although the initial motivation for category theory was far removed from foundationalism, the two fields turned out to have deep connections. As John Lane Bell writes: "In fact categories can themselves be viewed as type theories of a certain kind; this fact alone indicates that type theory is much more closely related to category theory than it is to set theory." In brief, a category can be viewed as a type theory by regarding its objects as types (or sorts), i.e. "Roughly speaking, a category may be thought of as a type theory shorn of its syntax." A number of significant results follow in this way:[6]

cartesian closed categories correspond to the typed λ-calculus (Lambek, 1970);
C-monoids (categories with products and exponentials and one non-terminal object) correspond to the untyped λ-calculus (observed independently by Lambek and Dana Scott around 1980);
locally cartesian closed categories correspond to Martin-Löf type theories (Seely, 1984).

The interplay, known as categorical logic, has been a subject of active research since then; see the monograph of Jacobs (1999) for instance.
See also

Data type for concrete types of data in programming
Domain theory
Type (model theory)
Type system for a more practical discussion of type systems for programming languages
Univalent foundations

Notes

Church, Alonzo (1940). "A formulation of the simple theory of types". The Journal of Symbolic Logic. 5 (2): 56–68. doi:10.2307/2266170. JSTOR 2266170.
Barendregt, Henk (1991). "Introduction to generalized type systems". Journal of Functional Programming. 1 (2): 125–154. doi:10.1017/s0956796800020025. hdl:2066/17240. ISSN 0956-7968.
Henk Barendregt; Wil Dekkers; Richard Statman (20 June 2013). Lambda Calculus with Types. Cambridge University Press. p. 66. ISBN 978-0-521-76614-2.
Heineman, George T.; Bessai, Jan; Düdder, Boris; Rehof, Jakob (2016). "A long and winding road towards modular synthesis". Leveraging Applications of Formal Methods, Verification and Validation: Foundational Techniques. ISoLA 2016. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. 9952. Springer. pp. 303–317. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-47166-2_21.
ETCS in nLab

Bell, John L. (2012). "Types, Sets and Categories" (PDF). In Kanamory, Akihiro (ed.). Sets and Extensions in the Twentieth Century. Handbook of the History of Logic. 6. Elsevier. ISBN 978-0-08-093066-4.

References

Farmer, William M. (2008). "The seven virtues of simple type theory". Journal of Applied Logic. 6 (3): 267–286. doi:10.1016/j.jal.2007.11.001.

Further reading

Aarts, C.; Backhouse, R.; Hoogendijk, P.; Voermans, E.; van der Woude, J. (December 1992). "A Relational Theory of Datatypes". Technische Universiteit Eindhoven.
Andrews B., Peter (2002). An Introduction to Mathematical Logic and Type Theory: To Truth Through Proof (2nd ed.). Kluwer. ISBN 978-1-4020-0763-7.
Jacobs, Bart (1999). Categorical Logic and Type Theory. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics. 141. Elsevier. ISBN 978-0-444-50170-7. Covers type theory in depth, including polymorphic and dependent type extensions. Gives categorical semantics.
Cardelli, Luca (1996). "Type Systems". In Tucker, Allen B. (ed.). The Computer Science and Engineering Handbook. CRC Press. pp. 2208–36. ISBN 9780849329098.
Collins, Jordan E. (2012). A History of the Theory of Types: Developments After the Second Edition of 'Principia Mathematica'. Lambert Academic Publishing. hdl:11375/12315. ISBN 978-3-8473-2963-3. Provides a historical survey of the developments of the theory of types with a focus on the decline of the theory as a foundation of mathematics over the four decades following the publication of the second edition of 'Principia Mathematica'.
Constable, Robert L. (2012) [2002]. "Naïve Computational Type Theory" (PDF). In Schwichtenberg, H.; Steinbruggen, R. (eds.). Proof and System-Reliability. Nato Science Series II. 62. Springer. pp. 213–259. ISBN 9789401004138. Intended as a type theory counterpart of Paul Halmos's (1960) Naïve Set Theory
Coquand, Thierry (2018) [2006]. "Type Theory". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Thompson, Simon (1991). Type Theory and Functional Programming. Addison–Wesley. ISBN 0-201-41667-0.
Hindley, J. Roger (2008) [1995]. Basic Simple Type Theory. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-05422-5. A good introduction to simple type theory for computer scientists; the system described is not exactly Church's STT though. Book review
Kamareddine, Fairouz D.; Laan, Twan; Nederpelt, Rob P. (2004). A modern perspective on type theory: from its origins until today. Springer. ISBN 1-4020-2334-0.
Ferreirós, José; Domínguez, José Ferreirós (2007). "X. Logic and Type Theory in the Interwar Period". Labyrinth of thought: a history of set theory and its role in modern mathematics (2nd ed.). Springer. ISBN 978-3-7643-8349-7.
Laan, T.D.L. (1997). The evolution of type theory in logic and mathematics (PDF) (PhD). Eindhoven University of Technology. doi:10.6100/IR498552. ISBN 90-386-0531-5.

Computer science
Note: This template roughly follows the 2012 ACM Computing Classification System.
Hardware

Printed circuit board Peripheral Integrated circuit Very Large Scale Integration Systems on Chip (SoCs) Energy consumption (Green computing) Electronic design automation Hardware acceleration


Computer systems
organization

Computer architecture Embedded system Real-time computing Dependability

Networks

Network architecture Network protocol Network components Network scheduler Network performance evaluation Network service

Software organization

Interpreter Middleware Virtual machine Operating system Software quality

Software notations
and tools

Programming paradigm Programming language Compiler Domain-specific language Modeling language Software framework Integrated development environment Software configuration management Software library Software repository

Software development

Control variable Software development process Requirements analysis Software design Software construction Software deployment Software maintenance Programming team Open-source model

Theory of computation

Model of computation Formal language Automata theory Computability theory Computational complexity theory Logic Semantics

Algorithms

Algorithm design Analysis of algorithms Algorithmic efficiency Randomized algorithm Computational geometry

Mathematics
of computing

Discrete mathematics Probability Statistics Mathematical software Information theory Mathematical analysis Numerical analysis

Information
systems

Database management system Information storage systems Enterprise information system Social information systems Geographic information system Decision support system Process control system Multimedia information system Data mining Digital library Computing platform Digital marketing World Wide Web Information retrieval

Security

Cryptography Formal methods Security services Intrusion detection system Hardware security Network security Information security Application security

Human–computer
interaction

Interaction design Social computing Ubiquitous computing Visualization Accessibility

Concurrency

Concurrent computing Parallel computing Distributed computing Multithreading Multiprocessing

Artificial
intelligence

Natural language processing Knowledge representation and reasoning Computer vision Automated planning and scheduling Search methodology Control method Philosophy of artificial intelligence Distributed artificial intelligence

Machine learning

Supervised learning Unsupervised learning Reinforcement learning Multi-task learning Cross-validation

Graphics

Animation Rendering Image manipulation Graphics processing unit Mixed reality Virtual reality Image compression Solid modeling

Applied
computing

E-commerce Enterprise software Computational mathematics Computational physics Computational chemistry Computational biology Computational social science Computational engineering Computational healthcare Digital art Electronic publishing Cyberwarfare Electronic voting Video games Word processing Operations research Educational technology Document management

Wikipedia book Book Category Category Outline Outline WikiProjectWikiProject Commons page Commons

vte

Mathematical logic
General

Formal language Formation rule Formal proof Formal semantics Well-formed formula Set Element Class Classical logic Axiom Rule of inference Relation Theorem Logical consequence Type theory Symbol Syntax Theory

Systems

Formal system Deductive system Axiomatic system Hilbert style systems Natural deduction Sequent calculus

Traditional logic

Proposition Inference Argument Validity Syllogism Square of opposition Venn diagram

Propositional calculus
and Boolean logic

Boolean functions Propositional calculus Propositional formula Logical connectives Truth tables Many-valued logic

Predicate logic

First-order Quantifiers Predicate Second-order Monadic predicate calculus

Naive set theory

Set Empty set Element Enumeration Extensionality Finite set Infinite set Subset Power set Countable set Uncountable set Recursive set Domain Codomain Image Map Function Relation Ordered pair

Set theory

Foundations of mathematics Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory Axiom of choice General set theory Kripke–Platek set theory Von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory Morse–Kelley set theory Tarski–Grothendieck set theory

Model theory

Model Interpretation Non-standard model Finite model theory Truth value Validity

Proof theory

Formal proof Deductive system Formal system Theorem Logical consequence Rule of inference Syntax

Computability
theory

Recursion Recursive set Recursively enumerable set Decision problem Church–Turing thesis Computable function Primitive recursive function

Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics

Graduate Texts in Mathematics

Graduate Studies in Mathematics

Mathematics Encyclopedia

World

Index

Hellenica World - Scientific Library

Retrieved from "http://en.wikipedia.org/"
All text is available under the terms of the GNU Free Documentation License